From: renfrod@central.edu (Dave L. Renfro)
Subject: Re: What is the point of rigor?
Date: 24 Oct 2000 00:47:08 -0400
Newsgroups: sci.math
Summary: [missing]
Martin Green
[sci.math Sun, 22 Oct 2000 22:28:49 GMT]
wrote
> Martin Green wrote:
>
>> > Are there any examples of....a mathematical result which
>> > appeared to be right, until the Bertrand Russell types had
>> > a go at it and found out that it was wrong?
>
> Dennis Feldman evaded answering:
>
>> Many; and major ones, at that. Have a look at the history of
>> analysis. Or the invention of fractals. Or Godel theorems...
>
> Did you even read what I wrote? I didn't ask for examples of
> new branches of mathematics....I asked if there were any cases
> of old results which were proven wrong by the application of
> "rigorous" methods.
The failure to distinguish between uniform and non-uniform
convergence of series of functions. [Early (before approx. 1820)
work in Fourier series.]
Assuming term-by-term integration of infinite series of functions.
[Many mathematicians, middle 1800's.]
The failure to distinguish between nowhere dense sets and sets
whose Jordan measure equals zero. [Du Bois-Reymond's, Hankel's,
etc. (approx. 1870 to 1885) work in integration theory.]
[From Thomas Hawkins' book, pp. 43-44] "Between the appearance
of Ampere's paper [in 1806] and 1870, the proposition that any
(continuous) function is differentiable in general [i.e. except
for points isolated from each other] was stated and proved in
most of the leading texts on the calculus." [Ten references to
incorrect proofs are given.]
Lebesgue's incorrect assertion (made without proof) in a very
highly regarded 1905 paper that the projection onto a line of
a G_delta set in the plane is a Borel set.
Here are some things I doubt would have been discovered without
the application of a fair amount of rigor: The existence of
transcendental numbers, nowhere differentiable continuous
functions, Banach-Tarski decompositions, Peano curves, Godel
incompleteness results, various independence results in ZFC,
real numbers whose decimal expansions cannot be coded up by the
use of a computer program, free ultrafilters on the natural
numbers, the additive group of real numbers is isomorphic to
the additive group of complex numbers [this one is for Pertti
Lounesto], Sierpinski-Zygmund functions, C^infinity functions
that are nowhere analytic, the fact that for each positive
integer n at least one of exp(e^n), exp(e^(2n)), exp(e^(3n)) is
transcendental, the prime number theorem, 2^(Aleph_0) pairwise
disjoint subsets of [0,1] that each have outer Lebesgue
measure 1, the set of non-continuity points of a function from
the reals to the reals can be exactly the set of transcendental
numbers but it cannot be the set of rational numbers, the subset
(rationals)^2 union (irrationals)^2 is a pathwise connected
subset of R^2, there exist non-measurable functions that satisfy
the intermediate value property, . . . . . . .
Dave L. Renfro
==============================================================================
From: wrameyxiii@home.remove13.com (Wade Ramey)
Subject: Re: What is the point of rigor?
Date: Tue, 24 Oct 2000 19:43:48 GMT
Newsgroups: sci.math
Summary: [missing]
In article , "Martin
Green" wrote:
> Looking at it intuitively, I'd
> say there are lots of zigzags there, and the sum of the series should be
> well-defined for any value of x.
My intuition disagrees. What do we do now, take a vote?
> I notice, by the way, that he did not see fit to provide an example
> of how you can get in trouble by integrating before summing, the way
> I gave an example of how you can get in trouble by differentiating.
That's on p. 15 of your local real analysis text. Here's a simple example.
On R, set f_n = 1 on [n, n+1], 0 elsewhere. Then f_n -> 0 pointwise
everywhere on R, yet the integral of f_n over R is 1 for all n. So the
integral of the limit is not the limit of the integrals. Because every
sequence can be viewed as a series, you have your example.
Wade
PS: Martin, I am enjoying your thread
==============================================================================
From: hrubin@odds.stat.purdue.edu (Herman Rubin)
Subject: Re: What is the point of rigor?
Date: 23 Oct 2000 21:06:51 -0500
Newsgroups: sci.math
In article <44OI5.24606$6O5.2255352@news1.rdc1.mb.home.com>,
Martin Green wrote:
>Martin Green wrote:
>> > Are there any examples of ...a mathematical result which appeared
>> > to be right, until the Bertrand Russell types had a go at it and found
>out
>> > that it was wrong??
Here is one in statistics. There are many problems which are
invariant under quite reasonable transformations. Objectivity
would say that invariant solutions are good. One can often
find out quite easily what the best invariant solution is.
However, there are reasonable problems for which this is very
definitely not the case. One may argue that the first one of
these found as not reasonable, but this led to the quite natural
ones which are known. The obtaining of a rigorous treatment
led to the type of previously known mathematical paradox which
were the natural counterexamples.
--
This address is for information only. I do not claim that these views
are those of the Statistics Department or of Purdue University.
Herman Rubin, Dept. of Statistics, Purdue Univ., West Lafayette IN47907-1399
hrubin@stat.purdue.edu Phone: (765)494-6054 FAX: (765)494-0558
==============================================================================
From: Pertti Lounesto
Subject: Re: Q: An example of a function
Date: Thu, 26 Oct 2000 07:35:44 +0300
Newsgroups: sci.math
Gerry Myerson wrote:
> If you're into books - remember books? - Gelbaum & Olmsted,
> Counterexamples in Analysis, is full of stuff like this.
There are other books on counterexamples. See
M. Capobianco, J. Molluzo: Examples and Counterexamples in
Graph Theory. North Holland, Amsterdam, 1978.
Ya.S. Dubnov: Mistakes in Geometric Proofs. Heath, Boston, 1963.
J.E. Forn\ae ss, B. Stens\o nes: Lectures on Counterexamples in
Several Complex Variables. Princeton UP, Princeton, NJ, 1987.
B.R. Gelbaum, J.H.M. Olmsted: Counterexamples in Analysis.
Holden-Day, San Francisco, 1964.
B.R. Gelbaum, J.H.M. Olmsted: Theorems and Counterexamples
in Mathematics. Springer, New York, 1990.
B. Hauchecorne: Les contre-exemples en math\'ematiques.
Ellipses, Paris, 1988.
S.M. Khaleelulla: Counterexamples in Topological Vector Spaces.
Springer, Berlin, 1982.
I. Lakatos: Proofs and Refutations. The Logic of Mathematical
Discovery. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1976.
P. Lounesto: Counterexamples in Clifford algebras with CLICAL,
pp. 3-30 in R. Ablamowicz et al. (eds.): Clifford Algebras with
Numeric and Symbolic Computations. Birkh\"auser, Boston, 1996.
J.P. Romano, A.F. Siegel: Counterexamples in Probability and
Statistics. Wadsworth & Brooks, Monterey, CA, 1986.
L.A. Steen, J.A. Seebach: Counterexamples in Topology. Holt,
Rinehart and Winston, New York, 1970. Springer, New York, 1978.
J. Stoyanov: Counterexamples in Probability. John Wiley, Chichester,
1987, 1997.
G.L. Wise, E.B. Hall: Counterexamples in Probability and Real Analysis.
Oxford University Press, New York, 1993.